What is it about the delusion of trompe l'œil
that makes such works interesting? After all, there is nothing fascinating
in a trompe l'œil painting until the delusion has been dispelled; and once
it has been dispelled, the work is most often of no more than minor aesthetic
interest. We enjoy examining an object endowed with the power to throw us
into a delusory state of mind after it has divulged its secret to us; looking
at it sends a shiver down our metaphysical spines much in the way we shiver
when we think about an accident in which we were almost involved; we stare
at it much as we might stare at the carcass of a wild animal that almost got
the better of us. A trompe l'œil picture is an epistemological close call,
a reminder that Descartes's evil being that continuously fills us with error
may be disguised as a benevolent painter. The point I wish to make therefore
is that what is interesting about a trompe l'œil painting arises in our minds
after the painting has ceased to trompe our yeux; it is
when we have ceased to be the unwitting targets of a practical joke, and we
have decided to reflect upon the experience we have just gone through, that
the painting acquires its meaning.
And then looking at a trompe l'œil painting after the delusion has been dispelled
is fascinating because it shows us how utterly preposterous was Ruskin's famous
idea of the "innocent eye." One tries in vain to be deluded again,
but one can't; at best we are impressed by an illusion, which we obtain by
actively cooperating with the artifices devised by the artist. But there is
always a sense of innocence lost, a banishment from paradise, a fool's paradise
to be sure, but paradise nevertheless.
I'm not totally convinced by this. I liked the previous
para better, where we were alternating between the naive and knowledgable
states. We may not be able to hold the naive state, but with a good trompe-l'oeuil
you keep cycling through it to re-experience it.
All illusionistic art other than trompe l'œil relies for its effect on
a collusion between the artist and the spectator. Consider illusionistic paintings
of architecture for a moment. None of these paintings places the spectator
at the center of projection at the moment the picture becomes visible. Is
this true? I thought that the Peruzzi room was oriented to the entrance? And
what about the Urbino Studiolo? For instance, Pozzo's imaginary architecture
in the Church of Sant'Ignazio looks lopsided unless it is seen from the yellow
marble disk in the center of the church's nave: Therefore, only a visitor
who would have asked to be led blindfolded to the prescribed vantage point
would see the painting correctly, as it were, at first sight; but to have
prepared one's experience so carefully presupposes prior knowledge of the
spectacle one was about to behold and enjoy. Most viewers deeply enjoy the
experience despite having first seen it lopsided and distorted. These viewers
are in mental collusion with the artist who designed and painted the illusionistic
architecture because they know full well that they are experiencing an illusion
when they view the ceiling from the center of projection.
This concept of mental collusion is similar to Coleridge's "willing suspension
of disbelief for the moment, which constitutes poetic faith" (1907, Book
II, Chapter 14, p. 6). The difference is one of degree: Willing suspension
of disbelief refers to a cognitive operation, a voluntary adoption of a certain
aesthetic attitude; by mental collusion with the artist, I mean an operation
much closer to the roots of perception, more on the order of a suggestion
than a frame of mind.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fig.6.17 The vase-face reversible figure.
|
|
The concept of mental collusion appears in non-aesthetic
perceptual contexts as well. For instance, certain illusions do
not occur spontaneously or involuntarily; they occur only after the viewer
is informed what he or she is expected to see. But once that knowledge is
imparted, there is little the viewer can do to escape its effect. As an example,
consider the experiment in which Girgus, Rock, and Egatz (1977) measured the
time it took observers to experience a figure-ground reversal in Rubin's (1915)
vase-face figure (see Figure 6.17), which was thought to spontaneously reverse
back and forth between the vase percept and the face percept. The observers
were high-school students who had never seen the Rubin figure before. Every
5 seconds, the experimenter tapped a pencil to mark the moment at which the
observer was to report what he or she was seeing in the figure. Every effort
was made to communicate to the observers that certain figures could be described
in more than one way, and that therefore their reports could differ from signal
to signal, but they were not told that the Rubin figure was reversible and
they were not told what the alternative descriptions could be. After having
obtained the observers' reports, the experimenter interviewed them to ascertain
whether unreported reversals had occurred at every tap. Even with this scoring
procedure, which was most likely to overestimate the number of reversals seen
spontaneously, only So ?5 percent of the observers
saw the figure reverse within the first minute of viewing, a figure that went
up to 6o percent within the first two minutes and to 65 percent within the
first three minutes. During the interview, observers were taught to see both
alternatives and to grasp the reversibility of the figure. Afterward, the
observers were tested again and, as expected, all of them reported reversals.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fig.6.18 A Necker cube formed by phenomenal
contours as a perceptual analog of willing suspension of disbelief.
|
|
To better clarify the notion of mental collusion, let
us look at the wonderful illusion invented by Bradley, Dumais, and Petry (1976;
see Figure 6.18). The initial impression one receives is of a white paper
cutout of a Necker cube superimposed on a sheet of white paper on which eight
black disks have been drawn in order to enable you to see the figure's critical
features. Even though there are no lines joining the corners, you see them,
an unconscious inference regarding the nature of the object that would create
this sort of configuration. You are not free to see or not to see these phenomenal
contours: even if you see the Necker cube as
I described it, you always see the contours. When you do, you also can see
the cutout as a representation of a three-dimensional object, and, because
the representation is ambiguous, you can see it reverse, as does the Necker
cube.
Now the interesting twist to this illusion comes when one's attention is drawn
to another way of interpreting the eight spots. Imagine a sheet of paper with
eight holes in it, and under it a sheet of black paper that can be seen through
the holes. Now suppose we took the white paper cutout of the Necker cube and
slipped it between these two sheets so that the critical features were visible
through the eight portholes in the top white sheet of paper. When you interpret
the figure in this fashion, you can still "see" the Necker cube,
and you can still experience reversals of its orientation, but you
do not see the phenomenal contours. The act of choosing to see
the cutout of the cube behind a page with holes in it rather than in front
of the page with spots on it is very much like a willing suspension of disbelief.
But once one has made a commitment to that suspension of disbelief, the world
we perceive is consistent with how we have chosen to perceive it. It is important
to remember that we are not in a position to reinterpret every facet of our
perceptual experience and to see how the implications of our choice propagate
through the remainder of our experience. But there are certain aspects of
experience that allow us to make such a choice, although, unfortunately, we
do not understand what gives them this power.10